Skip to main content

Steve Pinker on good reductionism, bad reductionism

Pinker contrasts "greedy" reductionism, which he rejects, with "good" reductionism , which he advocates (note the moralizing grade-school teacher language).

Good reductionism as he sees it is the sort that admits of different explanatory levels. Citing Hilary Putnam, he says that you can't explain why a round peg doesn't fit in a square hole by talking about what happens at the quantum level. The whole may be the sum of its parts, but we can grasp the one explanation of why the square peg doesn't fit into the round whole only by thematizing the whole (in this case, the peg and the hole) as such.

Digression: actually, a more adequate explanation must also talk about how forces at a micro level are responsible for the resistance we feel when pressing the non fitting parts together. An adequate explanation must include BOTH how the parts as such tend to interact and the configuration of the whole made of these non-matching parts (the square/round shapes [but aren't 'square' and 'round' really short-hand for the way many, many parts are related?]). I think Pinker and I would agree about this much.

But I would disagree with him about ontological reductionism. Or rather, Pinker doesn't acknowledge the distinction between epistemic reductionism (which he rejects) and ontological (which he accepts). He is a full-blown ontological reductionist (shall we call this "ontologically greedy reductionism"?), and this position has inherent problems. For example, if every whole (regardless of how we may conceptualize it) is the sum of its parts, then doesn't this lead to a kind of infinite regress (of wholes that are merely the sum of parts of parts of parts of parts... ad infinitum) BUT he seems to think he can deflect this and other possible criticisms of ontological reductionism by adopting an anti-reductionist epistemology. That is, he thinks that wholes in nature are nothing more than the sum of their parts (ontological reductionism); but recognizes that in order to understand how nature works one must think in terms of wholes (epistemological anti-reductionism).

It seems to me that the only way to avoid the problems of onto-reductionism is to affirm that some wholes are not simply the sums of their parts. Not every whole is machine-like in nature, even though some are. The central problem in the study of nature is to distinguish one from the other. And Pinker is not only fails to offer a solution; he seems clueless about the problem.

I have to relisten to chapter 4, as he also talks about the social/individual language use as a whole/part phenom. I am not clear about this, but he seems to me to treat language qua existing in society as a proper ontological whole rather and definitely NOT as being the sum of its parts (the parts being language as it is proper to individual communicators) This whole/part contrast seems to have a somewhat Cartesian pallor; for he treats the societal level as externally observable, while treating language in the individual is private, internal.

I must re-listen to make sure that I got this right, but it seems to me that he doesn't think in terms of language as in some sense being "amongst" commuicators. No sense of unity in manifold, of the common good, of the public yet non-measurable. Stuck in positivistic and categories, with a strong tendency toward atomism, even in treatment of linguistic activity. But recognizes that there is a need for contrast. Thus ends up with a dualism of sorts.

If my interpretation of him is right, then the question of how the public/private are related to each other in his schema would surely be embarrassing to him: how does the internal individual linguistic activity relate to the public, external one? A materialistic cognate of Cartesian dualism (we need a materialistic equivalent of the ghost in the machine how about the gnome inside the machine?).

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu