Skip to main content

The Fifth Way and evolution

The Fifth Way of arguing for the existence of God, according to Thomas Aquinas, is taken from the fact that non-cognizant things act for a purpose.  He believes that this shows that an intelligent being is directing things now to a goal.  This argument is not an intelligent design argument inasmuch as it does not argue from the present existence of purposive activity in a thing to a previous event in which the thing so acting was engineered to act in that manner.  Rather, Aquinas argues that the fact that a thing acts now to attain a goal implies that it is now being directed by an intelligent being toward that goal.

To a contemporary reductionist, this argument must seem quaintly mistaken, for what passes as purposive activity is really a mechanical process.  The sunflower's turning toward the sun is the result of the flower's components acting essentially like levers in a machine.  The same is true for all other things, both living and non-living.

One procedure thought to demonstrate the truth of this mechanistic view of nature is to recite the story of the origin of life from non-life and the evolution of cognizant living things from non-cognizant.  This story seems to the contemporary reductionist to show how everything presently in the living world is derived entirely from the inanimate world studied in physics and therefore can in principle be explained adequately in terms of the laws of physics that govern that inanimate world.

What if our examination of living things, and especially of ourselves, shows that reductionism must be false and even incoherent?  What then are we to make of biogenesis and evolution?

Without reductionism, the story of the origin of life and the evolution look very different.  Yes, they would still involve chance.  But  (if anti-reductionism is true, then) the chancy nature of biogenesis and evolution does not contradict the fact that the world of physics is like a seed ready, given the right conditions, to give rise to something greater than itself.  Just as a seed will grow only when the right conditions are present, so to will life arise only under the right circumstances.  But the readiness to give rise to something more is present in the world before that something more has come to be.

A reductionist might object that just as a seed has its disposition only because it has originated from earlier mechanical processes, so too our universe has the disposition to give rise to life only because of antecedent mechanical processes.  But that objection would not work for the universe or multiverse as a whole.  If a world governed solely by the laws of physics cannot give rise to something irreducible to itself, then it does not matter to teleology how many universes it took or how long the one multiverse took to give rise to cognizant, affective life: whenever or however it does give rise to that irreducible something more than can be accounted for by physics, it does so only in virtue of an internal disposition to do so.

We might compare the way in which biogenesis and evolution involve an interplay of internal disposition and chance with the way the same two factors are involved in the triggering of an IED, an improvised explosive device.  It may take years for a bomb that has been hidden to be triggered into exploding.  When that explosion happens is a matter of chance.  The precise circumstances under which it happens are a matter of chance.  But that it happens is not a matter of chance alone but of a confluence of chance and purpose.

When life forms are understood understood non-reductively, biogenesis and evolution are as much evidence of purpose as any found in nature.  In fact, you could construct a new version of the Fifth Way that takes its point of departure from the facts of biogenesis and evolution, while making room also for the role of chance in the origin and development of life.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu