Skip to main content

Melchisedech and Nietzsche

Nietzsche says that the priestly class invented good and evil in order to subvert society.  They wanted the nobles' power, but were too weak to overthrow them, so they outwitted them instead, convincing them that their quest for power was evil and inculcating them with a love of freedom, equality, and justice.  Such virtues and ideas made the nobles unwitting, de facto subjects of the priests.

It is worth noting, however, that Nietzsche also recognizes that the priests' influence didn't start with the invention of good and evil.  Prior to then, says N, the priests were responsible for leading ancestor worship.  Thus it seems that it was only because the priests were already influential in the community that they could change the minds of the nobles as they did with the invention of good and evil.

Contrast Nietzsche's account with the Old Testament story of Melchizedek, the first priestly figure described in the Bible (unless Able is a priestly figure):  M is not only a priest but the king (of Salem) as well.  He uses bread and wine to offer a sacrifice of thanksgiving in Abraham's name.  In the Old Testament version of this history, the need to give thanks and enter into a kind of communion with God comes before the Levitical priesthood's concern with expiating sin.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological...

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here....