Skip to main content

Adolph Portman, Schoenborn, useless beauty and play, columns v spandrels

In Chance or Purpose, Christoph Schoenborn points out that Adolf Portmann thought it significant that animals sometimes engage in playful activity that is useless but beautiful.  Schoenborn seems to think that this fact is an embarrassment to ateleological evolution or "evolutionism" (his term), but to my knowledge, he doesn't spell out exactly how it is so.

My first thought upon listening to Schoenborn's point is the likely retort that what is merely play to the individual (and may be useless for that individual's survival) may be useful to the species.  Such a point is like Dawkins' distinction between the way in which an activity may be viewed by the individual who engages in it (his example is of sex for pleasure) and the way in which it serves the species/gene pool (reproduction).  That distinction seems valid, at least to a point, but to let one's mind rest there would be to miss what I believe is Schoenborn's point.

I would develop the point in the following way.  We engage in intrinsically desirable activities simply because they are desirable, not because they are useful.  Yes, those that are useful may be more likely to survive in future generations.  So intrisically desirable activities survive only if they are useful.  But temporally speaking, they are able to contribute to survival because they were first regarded as intrinsically desirable rather than vice versa.  Utility comes from desirability.

One may object that playful activities may be ways of rehearsing already practiced useful activities.  Play fighting is a parody of real fighting.  So it would seem that, temporally speaking, the useful comes first. 

My reply would be that even those activities that seem merely useful have their origin in ones that are intrinsically desirable.  Animals fight only because they desire to eat.  Or in some cases because they enjoy the fight itself.

Of course, the animals eats to survive--or does it?  It eats to enjoy the flavor of its food as well as the feeling of a full stomach, and to avoid the pain of hunger.  When it comes to motivation, desire comes first.

There is something important about the primacy of desire.  Important even for human ethics.  Desire is forward-looking.  Explaining motivation by pointing to past utility can leave out desire.  It can look at nature like a machine in which everything moves as it does because it is pushed by something else.  This interpretation of nature treats the present simply as the result of the past.  But each past was what it was because of an inherent striving for the future.  The present is a continuation of that striving.  To understand the present one must grasp it in terms of its future-directedness.


It may be that a mechanistic approach to nature, by looking at the present as the inevitable result of the past is an unwitting anthropomorphism inasmuch as a whole is machine-like only if it functions as a machine for someone.

It may be that evolutionary utilitarianism inasmuch as it treats the useful as prior to the intrinsically desirable, is likewise an unwitting anthropomorphism inasmuch as it treats nature as a whole as if it were a either person engaged in instrumental reasoning or as a machine operated by someone.  Ditto with Dawkins' treatment of the selfish-gene.

Another thought: looking at the role of desire in motivating animals operation and comparing it to the past utility, etc.  I am reminded of the light/aperture metaphor that I used earlier.  That is, aspects of animal (and other) evolution that can be described in mechanistic terms complement the teleological aspects in a manner analogous to how an aperture lets in light.  More on that later, perhaps...

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu