Skip to main content

A better way of overcoming the false alternatives of dualism and reductionism: better than panpsychism and protopsychism

David Chalmers proposes protopsychism as part of an attempt to give an account of how it is that we have minds--an attempt to locate consciousness within nature.  I think this move and the positing of panpsychism are both motivated by the recognition of the need to overcome the assumptions that create the false dilemma of dualism vs. (reductive) materialism.

These two approaches get to the heart of the problem: they recognize that as the non-living things in the natural world are thought of as consisting only of the quantifiable, we won't be able to make room for cognition without seeming dualistic.  Those who recognize this problem respond by inserting something more than the Democritan quantifiable back into nature so sensation won't seem so radically different from the non-living things that humans and other sentient beings sense.

The Aristotelian approach is, I propose, less exotic, and less of a target for those ready to wield Ockham's razor.  It consists of affirming that non-living things have qualities that can't be exhaustively described quantitatively.  Non-living things are more than what Democritus thought they were, more than geometry in motion.  The common sense regard for qualities in nature is correct, at least partially.

Once one thinks of non-living things as having qualities irreducible to geometry in motion, it becomes possible to construct an account of how those qualities are related to the ones we associate with life.  We can articulate founding and founded relations between lower and higher levels of qualities.  We can talk about sensation as a re-presence of a lower level quality.

We no longer have to think of cognition, affection as an immaterial state somehow precipitated by an interaction of the immaterial with the material:  instead, we can think of perception as a higher-level quality of an organism, founded upon lower-level organic qualities.  Even this characterization may miss the mark somewhat, but it sure beats reductive materialism and dualism.

Back to panpsychism: it is an attempt to bridge the divide between living and non-living by making everything alive.  But while it may seem to suffice to do that bridging, it is not the only way to do that, and it seems rather exotic compared to the Aristotelian notion that non-living things have qualities in virtue of which they are more than geometry in motion.

A further criticism of  panpsychism might be to point out that the consciousness occurring at the lowest seems to be pointless.  To argue that we would have to analyze the alternative objects of consciousness to see if that objection is tenable.  That is, we'd have to ask if the lowest level psyche is aware of non-psyches, of itself or other psyches.  It can't be the first option without sacrificing the "pan" in pan-psychism.  Possessing self-awareness alone (the second option) would seem to be pointless.  As for the third, I'm not sure of what a panspsychist would say about the point of the lowest level psyche's awareness of other psyches.  In any case, it all seems hard to take that third option seriously when the Aristotelian approach gives us what we need--i.e., a continuum between non-living entities and living-sensing entities.  Why posit any more if this already suffices to avoid the pitfalls of both dualism and reductive materialism?

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu