Skip to main content

laws of nature and necessity: a thought experiment on necessity, laws of nature, Aquinas's Third Way and more

Materialists deny the existence of an immaterial necessary being while affirming that matter itself operates as it does necessarily.  They posit the laws of nature as the source of this necessity.

Aquinas argues for a self-necessary being in an interesting manner: starting with contingent beings, inferring that there must be at least one necessary being, distinguishing derived from underived necessity, and finally inferring the existence of a self-necessary being, i.e., one with underived necessity.  Also worth noting is the fact that part of this argument is said to commit the fallacy of composition.

What I'd like to  do here is explore (or perhaps it would be more accurate to say "invent") an analogy between the two ways of thinking.  My starting point is the suggestion, made by Sean Carroll and other scientists, that we are in a multiverse.

Here goes...

Suppose there is a multiplicity of universes, each with its own laws of nature, and that these universes arise through fluctuations in the quantum field.

That would mean that while each set of laws of nature seems to be necessary to those within its respective universe, it would not really be so.  Those laws could change.  But nevertheless, the way in which those laws change, and the way in which distinctive laws arise would itself be determined by laws of a higher order.  We might call those laws of the multiverse.  Of course, laws of the multiverse could change as well, but the way in which those laws change would itself be lawful, but in a manner that stands in preeminence over other multiversal laws.  We might call these preeminent laws meta-laws of the multiverse.  But there may be an orderly relationship among those preeminent laws, and that relationship itself may be regarded as the primordial, supereminent law of the universe.

If all of the above is not pure hogwash, well, then a few interesting points could be made regarding more parochial debates about laws of nature.

First of all, the necessity we ascribe to those laws must be qualified: these laws are only necessary in a parochial sense (quoad nos, we might say), for a law that holds necessarily in our universe might not hold at all in another (caveat: this qualification of their necessity does not bear upon the question of free will).

Secondly, that parochial necessity is derived from the relation of that local law to the supereminent law(s) of the universe.

Thirdly, all of the above is loosely analogous to some of the reasoning employed by Aquinas in his third way. For he infers the existence of a Being whose necessity is underived after he has argued that there must at least be necessary beings with underived necessity.  There is a kind of hierarchy sketched in the third way, as there is here with the talk of many not-quite-as-necessary-as-you-probably-thought laws of nature and the one law that is.

Fourthly, I think it right to criticize the overblown philosophical significance sometimes attributed to laws of nature.  The term "laws of nature" is a kind of metaphor for the pattern of operation that we discover in things in virtue of their dispositions.  In forgetting about how their concept of law begins with a metaphor, one can end up talking of laws almost as if they were more like lawmakers rather than disposition-governed patterns of action.  It is easy for one who is thus forgetful to commit the fallacy of misplaced concreteness: laws of nature might be said by them to exist before matter itself and tell matter how to behave.

Fifthly, we might rewind the above argument, keeping in mind that laws describe dispositions of individuals to act, and from there go on to try to construct a line of reasoning about the necessity and contingency that has to do with things acting (or not) according to their dispositions.  Starting with a local phenomenon, we might find a way of reasoning that ascends to the cosmic level in a manner paralleling what I did above with the laws of nature.  That sort of argument would look like Aquinas's third way, but it would not be about a necessary being but about a necessary disposition had by a being.  Methinks this first being would be analogous to the medieval notion of a primum mobile rather than to ens primum.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu