Skip to main content

Emergent properties and mechanism

Ignorance or near ignorance should never stop a blogger's blathering (what I am about to say is clearly consistent with the above principle):

The emergent property of a whole is not merely the sum of the interactions of its parts according to their individual, pre-emergent properties. Something more is going on: something new. If sentience is regarded as an emergent property, then no machine could be sentient, for the product of a machine's operations is nothing other than the result of the interactions its parts. Someone might object, however, that under certain circumstances new properties might emerge from from the interactions of the machine's parts. One can respond to this objection in either of two ways. First: definitionaly (sp?). If a machine IS a machine then it has no emergent operations. Period. Or (call this 1b) one might recast the same point in the form of a modem tollens argument: if machines can have emergent properties, then there is no reason in principle why all mechanical interactions could not have emergent properties. And in this case there really are no purely mechanical interactions; perhaps the cosmos is one big partially awake organism. At this point, speculative philosophy of science has merged with new age monism (at this point GK Chesterton's statement "Those who don't believe in God will believe in anything" comes to mind).

The other alternative is to look for patterns in the emergence of new properties. One guiding principle might be "operation follows being," which suggests a twofold sense of emergence: emergent operation and emergent being (in this context "being" means the characteristic in virtue of which something remains able to operate when it is not operating and in virtue of which it does operate when it does... for example, being able to see is a characteristic had by the eye/cortex/etc) . In other words, the upper level being of being emerges from the lower level, as does its respective operation(s). The inquiry into the genuineness of the claim that machines are really non-organic perceivers would consist in part in looking at for a law-like relationship between upper and lower levels in emergence, as well as whether there is an obvious reason for that relationship, whereupon we can apply this law to the case of computational machines in order to arrive at a sober judgment as to whether or not its operations are emergent.

[later addition: Perhaps this is a decent example of higher/lower relations as following a law-like pattern: Robert Penrose notes the plasticity of the brain as the substratum of long term memory. I would call this "plant-like," for the brain sorta grows differently on the basis of stored information. He also points out how this plasticity is unlike a machine. Animals have, if you will, a vegetative way of developing. Higher level of being (being able to remember) is embossed upon the lower level (growing differently)]

Note: it seems to me that emergence is just a materialist's way of admitting that Aristotle was right about form while still holding somewhat to a kind of "trickle up" theory of being.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu