Skip to main content

Chapter 1a: Reductive materialism

Materialism can be defined as the conviction that all beings that exist are made of matter, or at least that human nature is so constituted that the individual ceases to exist with the death of the body.  These positions are not the target of this chapter.  Rather, a somewhat extreme version called reductive materialism is all that I mean to address here.  The alternative that I will propose--we'll call it holism--will serve as a common sense position that we can use to evaluate reductive and other positions.

Reductive materialism claims that a human individual (and other animals) is nothing more than a collection of chemicals and that human action is nothing more than the complex chemical and mechanical interactions of those parts.  The whole that we call a human being is quite literally the sum of all of its parts.

This position is frequently called mechanistic because a machine really is the collection of its own parts.  If we see it as a whole, that is only because we impose our own interpretation upon many items that happen to have been brought together to serve our own purposes.  It makes sense to talk of machines as individuals, for we often interact with the machine as if it were a whole rather than with just one part in isolation from the others.  We think and talk of humans and other organisms as wholes too.  But we are deceiving ourselves, say reductive materialists, if we think of humans and other organisms as anything more than complex machines.

Why would anyone object to the reductive, mechanistic understanding of human nature?  One objection would be that we are able to know unchanging truths, such as the truths of mathematics, so that there must be something unchanging--and hence immaterial--about the human mind.  That is an interesting approach that deserves serious consideration.  But that is not the approach being offered here.  For objecting in that way may make it seem that we are stuck in a dilemma: on one side is reductive materialism and on the other is dualism, which posits the mind or soul as an immaterial thing that somehow interacts with the body.  I will argue later on that this is a false dilemma.  For the present, however, I propose that we look at how humans go about conducting their daily affairs and solving day-to-day problems.  This approach will give us a basis for criticizing reductive materialism without committing to dualism.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu