Skip to main content

Common law

Common law did not start off as legitimate law, but rather as an artful imposition by clerks working for a Norman conquerer.  It acquired legitimacy through acquiescence by subjects who respected its consistency and justice.  Common law today retains that legitimacy through its consistency with the past.  Sometimes -- when circumstances change -- common law must also change so as to adapt.  But that change is legitimate only inasmuch as it reaches into the past for a way to understand something new in the present.  By proceeding in this manner, the common law judge preserves the legitimacy of his judgments through their conformity with a kind of democracy of the dead.

Simply overturning common law because one detects -- not a new situation -- but a new principle is to undermine the legitimacy of common law.  Even if one believes this new principle is obvious to those formed by the spirit of the age, one cannot legitimately introduce it to a common law situation.  For common law has no procedure to legitimate the spirit of this age any more than it can the personal preferences of a judge.  The promulgation of new moral principles is the task of a legislator rather than a common law judge.

Dworkin's strategy is to avoid both the conservatism of a common law judge who only wants to duplicate the past as well as an "living Constitution" innovator who would introduce contemporary principles to common law.  He does this by allowing the common law judge to reach into the past to find principles not previously applied in the sort of case that one presently faces.  There is something both conservative about this procedure inasmuch as it reaches into the past, yet innovative inasmuch as it applies the already known principle in a new way.

There is something untethered about this:  for in applying old principles to new situations, the Dworkian judge is lifting the old principle to a higher level of generality than it previously had.  But if different judges did this to their preferred background principles, then these principles would enter into conflict with each other.  The integrity of the law -- the very thing that Dworkin is so concerned about preserving -- would break down.  For Dworkin cannot answer the question "whose background principles" in a principled manner.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

P F Strawson's Freedom and Resentment: the argument laid out

Here is a summary and comments on the essay Freedom and Resentment by PF Strawson.  He makes some great points, and when he is wrong, it is in such a way as to clarify things a great deal.  My non-deterministic position is much better thanks to having read this.  I’ll summarize it in this post and respond in a later one. In a nutshell: PFS first argues that personal resentment that we may feel toward another for having failed to show goodwill toward us would have no problem coexisting with the conviction that determinism is true.  Moral disapprobation, as an analog to resentment, is likewise capable of coexisting with deterministic convictions. In fact, it would seem nearly impossible for a normally-constituted person (i.e., a non-sociopath) to leave behind the web of moral convictions, even if that person is a determinist.  In this way, by arguing that moral and determinist convictions can coexist in the same person, PFS undermines the libertarian argument ...

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological...