Skip to main content

DD's hetero-phenomenology and my pretentious name for the alternative: "heemeis-phenomenology"

I am just beginning to listen to Daniel Dennett's Explaining Consciousness and am thoroughly enjoying it.  That is first of all because it is much less pompous than Freedom Evolves (although he does have a certain fondness for the word 'sophisticated').  Secondly, because he tells a good story.  It most certainly is not because what he has to say seems remotely close to the truth.

DD thinks that science can tell us all that's worth knowing about human nature, including what's worth knowing about the nature of knowledge itself.  Nagel and Searle, on the other hand, point to the need for the first person perspective to give us insights into aspects our humanity that cannot be obtained through scientific methodology.  By "first person perspective" I mean what it's like to to have experiences (including intentions, sensations, feelings, desires, etc.) to the one who is having them.  The systematic analysis of the first-person perspective is called "Phenomenology."  DD is no friend to phenomenology.  In fact, he claims that it practitioners neither agree with each other about the nature of experience nor are able to resolve their disagreements, since they rely on evidence that cannot be examined scientifically.  As an alternative to the first first-person centered approach he proposes his own, third-person centered approach, which he calls "hetero (other) phenomenology." It treats first-person reports (i.e., reports of having experiences) from a third person perspective.  Its practitioner is like an anthropologist, recording reports of experiences with a detachment about veracity that is much like a field anthropologist's registration of reports of Big Foot sightings.  Instead of being detached about the question of the actual existence of Big Foot, however, the hetero-phenomenologist brackets the existence of "Phenomen":  he copies down reports of the presence of Phanomen without making a judgment about the existence of that which is reported.  In this way, he does not distinguish between a genuine report of experience and one that is non-genuine( be it a randomly generated list of words; a word-string generated by a well-designed Turing machine, blather from a zombie, etc.).  He does not concern himself with what is unavailable for scientific query: in that way, he avails himself to (what he thinks is) the only genuinely scientific grasp of the issue

There is plenty to criticize in this proposal, but it's too early for me to do so.

Nevertheless, I take issue with his dismissive remark about phenomenology:  what if he is wrong because phenomenologists in fact agree with each other either entirely or for the most part? And supposing they disagree, what would be wrong with adjudicating on the basis of reflection upon one's own experience?  Isn't this analogous to adjudicating between scientific claims on the basis of experiments that one has conducted on one's own?

Think of an anthropologist visiting a society in which chemistry is purportedly practiced:  if the anthropologist simply copies down the reports of scientific discovery, then he is more or less a mere sociologist of scientist--nothing more.  If he stops to look at the evidence himself, however, he is acting like a chemist himself and not just a mere sociologist.  A hetero-phenomenologist (HD) as defined by DD is not a phenomenologist at all, but a sociologist of phenomenology.

I suppose that later on in the book DD will anticipate this objection and point out that the HD can also use natural science to corroborate the reports.  But arguing against that reply so early on would be putting words in his mouth--or in his text.

Let me point out that practically every sentence in which he discusses HD begins with the word "we."  DD does not believe in basing rational inquiry upon statements about evidence that are originally given in the first person singular, but he is totally comfortable with the first person plural.  Perhaps the best response to DD's proposal is to propose a method that he himself practices: what is apparent to us rather than what is apparent to the "I" or ego.  Perhaps a phenomenology of the we is more accessible than that DD's third-person and Husserl's first person singular phenomenologies.

Take the notion of evidence, for example.  How is it that we come to use this word?  Is there a scientific answer?  I don't think so, for science presupposes that this word is meaningful.  The first answer to this question about evidence, therefore, is what we recognize together as evidence.  But "recognize" and "we" are likewise pre-scientific terms upon which science must depend.  The study of evidence, therefore, takes us into a region that must be objective but which cannot be justified by scientific reasoning.  Perhaps science cannot do so because it is a phenomenon.  And perhaps it is precisely the sort of phenomenon about which DD cannot be indifferent.

These are all suggestions: I need to think about this more.  Meanwhile, I am inclined to dig up the Greek word for "we" (Heemeis) and prefix it to the term "phenomenology" to form the name of phenomenology that DD presupposes in introducing his own, yet which done in the first person (albeit plural rather than singular)

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological...

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here....

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han...