Skip to main content

needed: an ethology of freedom-as-an-achievement

That is, one who thinks that Benjamin Libbet's experiment could be used to disprove the existence of any free choice whatsoever has not thought clearly about the various contexts in which we may find ourselves making a choice.   Common to those contexts is a prior deliberation that follows upon an oftentimes creative exploration of different possible courses of action.

When we look different choices made at different times, we see that they vary to a very great degree and that this difference may be quite relevant to the question of freedom.  In fact, it may be that some choices seem freer than others.  Consider how the agent may consider different courses of action solely in instrumental terms, i.e., neither as desirable or undesirable in themselves.  In another situation, however, the agent may be deciding between means that are themselves instrinsically desirable or undesirable. Consider also how the goal that spurs deliberation may be something of only very immediate significance or it may have to do with the point of one's whole life.  As we go from younger to older, from more selfish to more generous, from vicious to virtuous, we may become better at making choices that are fulfilling, and in that sense we may be freer to attain what we are ultimately seeking.  These considerations suggest that freedom is better thought of as an achievement rather than as an underlying property. Our inquiry into the nature of freedom must note the differences to be found in the ends and means that we are considering when deliberating and choosing.  Without noting these differences, we run the risk of talking about freedom in a manner that is so abstract, that it fails to be applicable to any concrete choices.  That, unfortunately, is precisely what happened to Daniel Dennett and to others who draw conclusions about the nature or existence of freedom from Benjamin Libbet's experiment.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological...

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here....

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han...