Skip to main content

response to P F Strawson

Below is my response to P F Strawson (I summarized him in a prior post).


PF Strawson argues that one who believes in determinism will continue to engage in interpersonal relationships in a manner that shows concern about morality; therefore, the libertarian argument against determinism is undermined, for it claims that determinism is at odds with morality.


I will argue (or rather, in this blog post I will sketch an argument to the effect) that while a vague belief in determinism may be able to coexist with moral convictions, neither desire, moral convictions nor positive freedom (that is, freedom as defined in Strawson's essay) could come into existence if a specific form of determinism were true. Key to this argument is the claim that there is not just one kind of determinism but many, which vary according to the various ways in which one might attempt to justify this claim. A theist who is committed to determinism, for example, might give metaphysical reasons for thinking that the operation of the human will is predetermined by a provident Deity; a neo-Platonic determinist might argue that human volition originates from a higher immaterial being whose existence and operation is itself the result of an emanation from a still higher being, etc., all of which ultimately emanates necessarily from a non-provident Deity; a non-reductive materialist who is committed to determinism might argue that human volition results in a lawlike manner from the interaction of a human being with its environment; and a reductive determinist (i.e., a reductive materialist who is committed to determinism) would argue that the operation of the will is predetermined by antecedent material conditions.

Although there are many kinds of determinism, my argument focuses only on how determinism cannot rely upon a reductively materialist justification, because the reductive materialist account of desire, free will, and moral convictions is false. I leave untouched the question of whether some other form of determinism may be compatible with positive freedom. In this way, my argument's central conclusion does not so much contradict PF Strawson's conclusion as marginalize it. It concedes that one who comes to believe in determinism will find it natural to continue adhering to moral convictions and that determinism generaliter may be consistent with belief in a positive free will (as defined by Strawson). But reductive determinism, precisely because it is reductive, is not compatible with free will inasmuch as no such will could exist.


One question not yet addressed is whether some version of non-reductive materialism could both avoid the reductionism's incoherence and provide a justification either for determinism or for its contrary. Instead of arguing that determinism is true or false, I will argue that the correct answer hinges upon a more adequate definition of freedom than Strawson's "positive freedom."  A phenomenology of practical reasoning shows that we have reasons for our choices, but those reasons do not determine which choice we make.  Determinism seems less plausible to the degree that one takes this indetermination in our reasons as an indetermination in re; determinism seems more plausible inasmuch as one regards this indetermination as a surface phenomenon, with determining factors  being at work under the surface.  


Digression: I love how Strawson rightly avoids justifying the truth of moral convictions. It is clear that for him, the meaningfulness as well as truth of such convictions is to be found only by one who is concerned about the attitude of others, and that this concern arises as a result of one's interactions with others. He calls this concern a "participatory" attitude, for one who takes on this attitude participates in community life. This anti-foundationalist approach seems right on target. I would suggest, however, that moral convictions arising from interpersonal interactions lead us to expect to find other rational agents who have already arrived at the same conclusion, so that to adopt such convictions is inseparable from identifying oneself as a member of the community of rational agents, a community whose membership is open-ended and may even extend beyond humanity itself.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological...

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here....

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han...