Skip to main content

laws of nature, how materialists end up positing something like God

I am writing this with unfair moves made by evangelical atheists in mind:

Suppose the laws themselves may change through time: if they do, the way in which they change is itself a law of nature.  And if there are many such laws, then the way in which the laws themselves are related to each other might be a kind of law of nature.  So that there is one ultimate law of nature, the knowledge of which would explain everything else.

Suppose the laws that we know do not change through time: then one arrives at the conclusion regarding one ultimate law even more quickly.

To one who sees the connection between the laws we observe an this one supreme law, the following conditional is true:
if the more obvious laws are true, then the supreme but least obvious one is true.

The contrapositive is likewise true:
If the supreme but least obvious law is not true, then neither are the purportedly more obvious laws.

What is logically prior (what is known first by us) is the law or set of laws describing more obvious patterns of changes.  What is ontologically prior is the law underlying all other laws: it is known later on but it is more fundamental than the rest.  To really understand that there is such a fundamental law is to see how the more obvious ones entail it.

***

The difference between logical priority and ontological priority is pretty much parallel to what we see in theistic reasoning.

The theist reasons thus:  if there is teleological motion, order in causality, a universe in which there is some contingency but continuity in being, degrees of goodness (and if each of these is interwoven with the rest), then there is a supreme source of each of these.

The contrapositive is likewise true: if there is no supreme Being, then there is no change, no order in causality etc.

In both cases, to oppose the conclusion (there is a most fundamental law; there is a supreme Being) by arguing that the adherent is trying to infer the obvious (there is this or that law; there is an order of causality) from the non-obvious (from the fundamental law; from the Supreme Being) is to argue unfairly: it is to confuse the ontological priority stated in the contrapositive version with the logical priority stated in the other, original version (in which it is stated that if the more obvious but less fundamental reality exists, then the less obvious one exists).

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu