Skip to main content

Prosopagnosia and appropriation; signals from the central nervous system and appropriation

Note to self: prosopagnosia would serve as a good example of what I'm calling 'appropriation," I got the notion from Aquinas's commentary on Aristotle's De sensu, where he points out that the common sense (koine aesthesis for Ari, sensus communis for Thomas) takes the act of the proper sense and makes it its own.  It doesn't repeat the act of sensing, say, color: instead, it perceives something about color.  Somewhere (methinks) in the Summa theologiae (and in the other Summa) Aquinas talks about the relation of the higher to the lower power in a similar manner (but while making more neo-Platonic sounding points).
It seems to me that perhaps what we know about the brain today largely corroborates all this.  There is an appropriation by one part of the brain of the act done in another part of the brain (all of these acts are acts of the ensouled body and/or the embodied soul, but never mind for now).  But it may be the case that the "higher/lower" conception might not fit: the appropriation might be more "sideways" than "higher/lower." That is, for example, thanks to the discovery of the malady prosopagnosia, we recognize that there is a part of the brain that recognizes faces.  When this part works as one would hope it does, it certainly appropriates without duplicating the perception of proper and common sensible features of the face: we don't perceive the shape and color of the face twice: rather, through the face-recognition part of the brain we perceive the shaped and colored part of the world as the face of this or that someone whom we know from the past.  There is something anti-reductive in all this, inasmuch as one power is appropriating what another has done in a way that more "semantical" than "syntactical."

Once we recognize appropriation, we can criticize much "brain-talk" as unwarrantedly mechanistic.  Think of how we might say that the visual cortex appropriates the operation of some other part of the brain.  Ultimately, we can backwards and backwards with this appropriation talk until we get to our encounter with light coming into the eye.  At that point, it's worth noting that the organism as a whole in a sense appropriates its environment.  For each animal at each moment, it has an environment in a manner analogous to how (a Husserlian would say that ) a person has a world.  And perhaps Hans Jonas would say a nescient organism appropriates its environment as well.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu