Skip to main content

What if someone thought an integrated circuit was an organism? computer programmer, engineer, biologist, causal connections, connectionism, reductionism, fads

What if a biologist thought or pretended to think that an integrated circuit was an organism?  He would look for signs of life.  And what would he find?  No food intake.  No breathing. No chemical excretions.  No reproduction. No aging.  No death.  No life.

He would find responses to stimuli, but they might be different than the sort of responses that a computer programmer would expect.  After trying many different levels of electrical inputs, he will note corresponding outputs.  Whereas the computer programmer will think of input and output in binary terms -- either on or off -- the biologist will look for non-linear relationships.  And he might just find some.  Of  course (no surprise to either the biologist/electrician or to the engineer), he will note that certain levels of input will be catastrophic.

What if neurons perform their instrumental role in perception etc. precisely in virtue of their CAUSAL interrelations, AND these interrelations correspond to non linear functions rather than to the all-on or all-off functions that preoccupy a computer programmer?  In such a case, since the true causal relationship between each cell will be invisible to the computer programmer, so too will the physical basis of the operations (cognition, appetition, effort) associated with the brain.

IF a person whose day job is to design computer chips were made aware of the vast array of non-linear functions that characterize the input/output of a cell, he might make something that would simulate that sort of interaction.  But this would be a simulation rather than a duplication.  In fact, the simulation of just ONE cell may require a computer or even a supercomputer.  And simulating the interactions of billion of neurons in a brain may be a bit too complicated for the designer.

Let's suppose, however, that the designer COULD make a computer chip that interacts with others in a manner analogous to how cells interact: to do this correctly, he would have to go back to school and learn cell biology.  In such a case, the engineer would be able to set aside all of his pre-connectionist speculations about artificial intelligence in terms of ones and zeros.  Bio-chemistry rather than good old-fashioned artificial intelligence would supply the understanding needed to create this chip.

It would seem that computational theories might have to be trashed, and they will be replaced by the effort to use nanotechnology to create artificial neurons.

***

Afterthought:  one who objects that cells can be thought of in terms of output/input rather than in terms of causal relationships internal to the cell has no right to object to the Chinese Room argument, for he is treating the cell like a miniature Chinese Room.  In other words, while the CRA might not defeat connectionism generaliter, it does defeat the sort of connectionism that treats individual neurons in the same way that a functionalist treated the whole computer (I have to say this more clearly, but no time for doing that now).  It follows that we could characterize connectionism as a kind of retreat from a more mechanical to a more organic conception of cognition.  But perhaps it is not enough of a retreat.  Perhaps a surrender is called for.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Dembski's "specified compexity" semiotics and teleology (both ad intra and ad extra)

Integral to Dembski's idea of specified complexity (SC) is the notion that something extrinsic to evolution is the source of the specification in how it develops. He compares SC to the message sent by space aliens in the movie "Contact." In that movie, earthbound scientists determine that radio waves originating in from somewhere in our galaxy are actually a signal being sent by space aliens. The scientists determine that these waves are a signal is the fact that they indicate prime numbers in a way that a random occurrence would not. What is interesting to me is the fact that Dembski relies upon an analogy with a sign rather than a machine. Like a machine, signs are produced by an intelligent being for the sake of something beyond themselves. Machines, if you will, have a meaning. Signs, if you will, produce knowledge. But the meaning/knowledge is in both cases something other than the machine/sign itself. Both signs and machines are purposeful or teleological

continuing the discussion with Tim in a new post

Hi Tim, I am posting my reply here, because the great blogmeister won't let me put it all in a comment. Me thinks I get your point: is it that we can name and chimps can't, so therefore we are of greater value than chimps? Naming is something above and beyond what a chimp can do, right? In other words, you are illustrating the point I am making (if I catch your drift). My argument is only a sketch, but I think adding the ability to name names, as it were, is still not enough to make the argument seem cogent. For one can still ask why we prefer being able to name over other skills had by animals but not by humans. The objector would demand a more convincing reason. The answer I have in mind is, to put it briefly, that there is something infinite about human beings in comparison with the subhuman. That "something" has to do with our ability to think of the meaning of the cosmos. Whereas one might say"He's got the whole world in His han

particular/universal event/rule

While listening to a recorded lecture on Quine's Two Dogmas of Empiricism, it occurred to me that every rule is in a way, a fact about the world. Think about baseball: from the p.o.v. of an individual player, a baseball rule is not a thing but a guide for acting and interpreting the actions of others.  But this rule, like the action it guides, is part of a concrete individual --i.e., part of an institution that has come into existence at a particular place and time, has endured and  may eventually go out of existence.  The baseball rule, as a feature of that individual, is likewise individual.  The term "baseball rule," on the one hand, links us to a unique cultural event; it can, on the other hand, name a certain type of being.  In this way, it transgresses the boundary between proper and common noun. If there were no such overlap, then we might be tempted to divide our ontology between a bunch of facts "out there" and a bunch of common nouns "in here.&qu